by Pope St. Gelasius I
Introduction
Text
PDF
Introduction
by
Edmund Waldstein, O.Cist.
Pope St. Gelasius I’s letter to the Emperor Anastasius I Famuli vestrae pietatis, better known as Duo Sunt,[1] written in 494, is the classical statement of the Church’s teaching on the relation of the authority of pontiffs to the power of worldly rulers. It was to be quoted and paraphrased again and again by later popes. The key passage has been translated numerous times, but until now there have been only two complete translations into English, neither of which is in the public domain.[2] As the context of the letter is particularly important for understanding the meaning of the key passage correctly, we are pleased to offer the following collaborative translation of the whole letter on The Josias.[3]
St. Gelasius’s Life and Times
St. Gelasius reigned from 492-496,
when the Roman Empire had collapsed in the West, and Italy was ruled by
barbarians, who stood in an ambiguous relationship to the Byzantine emperor—at
times recognizing his authority, at other times styling themselves “kings” of
Italy. In 476 (conventionally seen as the end of the Empire) Odoacer, who was
already in power, had forced Romulus Augustulus to abdicate. In 493, the year
after St. Gelasius’s accession to the See of Peter, the Arian Ostrogoth
Theodoric the Great killed Odoacer, and established his rule in Italy.[4]
In the unsettled situation of Italy, the pope was an important source of order
for the city of Rome and beyond. Bronwen Neil and Pauline Allen have shown how
St. Gelasius was a “micro-manager” of the ecclesiastical, social, and political
affairs of Rome in a manner reminiscent of St. Gregory the Great a century
later.[5]
Gelasius was “a Roman born,” as he
himself testifies (§1 below), and the Liber
pontificalis notes that he was “of African nationality.”[6]
In “the African Gelasius,” writes Hugo Rahner, in the slightly histrionic tone
of his book on the liberty of the Church, “the ideals of Augustine and the
devotion of Leo for the Roman See were combined with a will of steel and
eloquence of style.”[7]
Not everyone has been so admiring of Gelasius’s style.[8] Nor
has everyone credited him with a will of steel.[9] But
it is certainly true that Gelasius was formed in the traditions of St.
Augustine and of St. Leo the Great. Dionysius Exiguus, who probably did not
know Gelasius personally, but knew many others who had known him, writes of him
in glowing terms as an exemplary pastor and scholar.[10]
The Acacian Schism
Although Gelasius was pope for less
than five years, a large number of documents from his pontificate have come
down to us,[11]
as well as several letters thought to have been drafted by him as a deacon
under his predecessor Pope Felix II/III (reigned 483-492).[12] Famulae vestrae pietatis is by far the
most famous of his letters. It was written in the context of the Acacian
Schism, the first major schism between Rome and Constantinople.
The schism had originated in the
Emperor Zeno’s attempt to reestablish ecclesial unity with the many Egyptian
Christians who had rejected the Council of Chalcedon (451). Chalcedon had
condemned the monophysite heresiarch Eutyches, and deposed the Alexandrian
patriarch Dioscurus, appointing Proterius in his stead.[13] In
457 the Alexandrian mob elected Timothy the Cat patriarch, and murdered
Proterius.[14]
Timothy died in 477, and his followers elected his ardent disciple Peter the
Hoarse to succeed him.[15]
In 482 Zeno sent out a formula of
faith, the Henotikon, to the
Egyptians.[16]
The document was not heterodox in its Christological statements. But it was unacceptable
to Rome from an ecclesiological point of view. Its underlying assumption was
that the emperor could define the faith (“Caesaropapism”). Moreover, it was
“political theology” in the derogatory sense, seeing the unity of faith as
being ordered to the unity of the empire, “the origin and composition, the
power and irresistible shield of our empire.”[17] But
what was least acceptable to Rome was its cavalier dismissal of Chalcedon, the
great triumph of the teaching of Pope Leo. After emphasizing that the only creed is the one defined at Nicea I
and Constantinople I, Zeno writes, “But we anathematize anyone who has thought,
or thinks, any other opinion, either now or at any time, whether at Chalcedon or at any Synod whatsoever.”[18]
Peter the Hoarse accepted the Henotikon, and Acacius, Patriarch of
Constantinople accepted him into communion, and was therefore excommunicated by
Pope Felix II/III in 484.[19]
This was the beginning of the Acacian Schism, which was to last till 519.
Acacius himself died in 489.[20]
His successor, Fravitta tried to assure both Pope Felix and Peter the Hoarse
that he was in communion with them.[21] In
491 the Emperor Zeno was succeeded by Emperor Anastasius I (491-518), who had
monophysite sympathies and continued Zeno’s policy.[22]
Famuli vestræ pietatis
When Gelasius was elected to the See
of Peter in 492 he did not write to the
Emperor Anastasius to announce his election, as was customary. But two
Romans, Faustus and Irenaeus, having been in Constantinople as part of a
legation from Theodoric the Great, brought word to him that the Emperor was
offended by his failure to write. This was the occasion of Famuli vestræ pietatis.
Gelasius begins the letter by excusing
himself for not having written before and addresses the Emperor patriotically
as the Roman princeps. He hints that
his desire to supply “something (however little) lacking from the fullness of
the Catholic Faith” in Constantinople, by which he means that he wants to bring
the schism to an end (§1). He then clarifies his right to do this by explaining
the relation of his “sacred authority” to the “royal power” of the Emperor—
this is the celebrated locus classicus for
the relation of lay and clerical authority (§2). He further explicates this by
laying out the primacy of the Apostolic See—the “firm foundation” laid by God
(§3). He then tries to persuade the Emperor to end the schism, by having
Acacius’s name deleted from the diptychs,
the lists of names prayed for in the Divine Liturgy (a sign of ecclesial
communion). Acacius was in Communion with heretics and should be condemned with
them. (§§4-9). He rebuffs the objection that removing Acacius from the diptychs
would cause a rebellion at Constantinople, and urges the emperor that he is
even more bound to combat heresy than he would be bound to combat offenses
against temporal laws (§§10-11). Finally, he defends himself against the charge
of arrogance, by turning the accusation against those who, contrary to the
tradition of the Fathers, refuse to submit to the Apostolic See (§12).
Auctoritas and Potestas
“For there are two, O emperor
Augustus, by which the world is principally ruled: the sacred authority (auctoritas) of pontiffs and the royal
power (potestas).” This famous line
was to be cited in favor of rival medieval theories of the relation of the two:
curialists cited it in favor of papal supremacy while their opponents cited it
to prove imperial or royal autonomy.[23]
More recently, it has been cited by Whig Thomists in favor of American-style
“religious freedom.”[24]
Its meaning continues to be debated among historians.
The modern debate has tended to focus
on the meaning of the terms auctoritas
and potestas. Erich Caspar argued
that auctoritas meant something like
moral influence, whereas potestas meant
coercive power:
In Roman constitutional law there was a clear distinction between the conceptually and morally superior auctoritas, founded on tradition and social standing, which the senate, for example, enjoyed, and a potestas equipped with executive power, which in republican times belonged only to the people and was delegated to their officials only for a set period of office.[25]
Caspar approached things from a
typically modern understanding of power dynamics, but a similar reading of the auctoritas and potestas distinction has been given by authors less in thrall to Realpolitik. Allan Cotrell notes that
some see potestas as “the mere
ability to use force without legitimate authority.’”[26]
Michael Hanby has recently argued for such a view.[27]
According to Hanby auctoritas “possesses
no extrinsic force,” but compels “by its own self-evidence.”[28]
To the extent that it is not bound and guided by auctoritas, potestas is “an indeterminate force, the brute strength
to realize arbitrary possibilities.”[29]
Readings such as Hanby’s cannot,
however, be sustained. As Walter Ullmann showed, the popes of the fifth century
saw themselves as having the authority to enact laws backed up by sanctions.[30]
That is, their auctoritas did possess
an extrinsic as well as an intrinsic
force. But it is clear also that Gelasius does not see the emperor’s potestas as mere brute force—he sees it
also as a moral authority that binds the consciences of subjects: “inasmuch as
it pertains to the order of public discipline, even the bishops themselves obey
your laws, knowing that rule [imperium]
has been bestowed to you from on high” (§2). Auctoritas and potestas are
more similar than such authors think. Caspar himself seems to admit as much,
when he goes on to argue that Gelasius’s letter was meant to bring the two
concepts closer together:
What was new and important was that Gelasius I now defined the state’s potestas and papal auctoritas (which functioned as potestas ligandi et solvendi) as ‘the two things… through which this world is ruled,’and thereby put them on the same level as commensurable magnitudes in the same conceptual category.[31]
Ullmann argued for a different
interpretation of the auctoritas-potestas
distinction. According to him, auctoritas
meant sovereign authority, whereas potestas
meant delegated authority:
Auctoritas is the faculty of shaping things creatively and in a binding manner, whilst potestas is the power to execute what the auctoritas has laid down. The Roman senate had auctoritas, the Roman magistrate had potestas. The antithesis between auctoritas and potestas stated already by Augustus himself, shows the ‘outstanding charismatic political authority’ which his auctoritas contained. It was sacred, since everything connected with Roman emperorship was sacred emanating as it did from his divinity. It was therefore all the easier to transfer these characteristically Roman ideas to the function of the Pope and to his auctoritas.[32]
While Ullmann is essentially right
about how Gelasius saw his relation the emperor, he is wrong to put so much weight
on the semantic distinction between auctoritas
and potestas. Ernst Stein and
Aloysius K. Ziegler showed convincingly that Gelasius did not mean to make any
semantic distinction between auctoritas and
potestas at all. For reasons of style
he did not wish to use the same word twice in the same sentence, and therefore he
used synonyms. In his damning review essay on Caspar, Stein points out that in Tractate IV, written only two years
after Famuli vestræ pietatis, Gelasius
writes of “both powers” (potestas utraque),
showing that he was quite willing to use potestas
to refer to the pontifical auctoritas.[33]
Ziegler, for his part, looks at the letters of Felix II/III, drafted by
Gelasius as a deacon, and finds conclusive evidence for Stein’s thesis in
Felix’s Epistle XV:
These things, most reverent Emperor, I do not wrest from you as vicar of the blessed Peter, by the authority of the apostolic power as it were [auctoritate velut apostolicae potestatis], but I confidently implore you as an anxious father desiring that the welfare and prosperity of my most clement son endure long.[34]
Perhaps Epistle XV is using the two terms in slightly different senses, but
it is clear that it sees both as belonging to the Apostolic See.[35]
Gelasius’s Integralism
George Demacopoulos has recently
argued that the scholarly focus on the semantic distinction between auctoritas and potestas is regrettable, since with “that singular focus, scholars
have failed to acknowledge many of the other significant moves that Gelasius
makes in the letter.”[36]
On that I think he is right. He is wrong, however, to fault Caspar and Ullmann
(especially the later) for reading Gelasius too much in the light of the
subsequent development of the papacy.[37]
Demacopoulos argues on historical-critical grounds, but it is hard not to see
his approach as being motivated by Greek Orthodox suspicion of Catholic
teaching on the papacy. Even from a purely historical perspective, it is
helpful to look at the developments to which a teaching gives rise to
understand it better. As St. John Henry Newman put it, the principle that “the
stream is clearest near the spring” does not apply to the development of a
teaching or belief, “which on the contrary is more equable, and purer, and
stronger, when its bed has become deep, and broad, and full.”[38]
And, of course, this is all the more true if it is a question of interpreting
the authoritative teachings of the Church. Since the bishops of Rome teach
under the guidance of the Holy Spirit, their pronouncements can only be
adequately understood in the light of later developments. Thus Gelasius ought
to be read in the light of the authoritative teachings of St. Gregory VII,
Innocent III, and Boniface VIII.
It is, therefore, all the more
significant that, despite his methodological shortcomings, Demacopoulos
ultimately comes to a reading of Gelasius very close to Ullmann’s. He argues,
namely, that Gelasius is indeed teaching a certain subordination of the
imperial under the pontifical power:
Among Gelasius’ impressive rhetorical demonstrations is his transformation of the argument for the divine derivation of imperial authority into an argument for the subordination of the emperor to the priesthood. […] Noting that imperial governance is a beneficium from God for which the emperor will be accountable, Gelasius quickly notes that he too will personally be required to render an account before God for whether or not Anastasius properly administers the imperial beneficium. In other words, Gelasius boldly inserts himself into the ruling/responsibility paradigm to imply that his own responsibility (and, therefore, his own authority) was superior to that of the emperor. The emperor, of course, retains a certain responsibility for the Roman population, but above that hierarchical paradigm exists another, more exalted layer, placing the pope between the emperor and God.[39]
The “hierarchical paradigm” to which
Demacopoulos refers is founded on a teleological understanding of society and
authority. No one grasped this more firmly than Walter Ullmann. That is why,
despite his exaggeration of the auctoritas-potestas
distinction, I still think Ullmann the best reader of Gelasius.
“Gelasias,” Ullman argues, “bequeathed
to all Papal generations a set of ideas based upon an interpretation of history
in the light of Christian teleology.”[40]
This Christian teleology sees the Church as a body with many members who have
distinct functions related to the single spiritual end of communion with God.
The members of this body belong to it with all that they are: “Christianity
seizes the whole of man and cannot, by its very nature, be confined to certain
departmental limits.”[41]
The Christian Body therefore “is not merely a pneumatic or sacramental or
spiritual body, but also an organic, concrete and earthy society.”[42]
In this visible society there are certain functions which are immediately
directed to its end, what Gelasius calls “the distribution of the venerable
mysteries,” (infra §2) and there are others which are mediately directed to its
end—everything, for example, that serves the preservation of bodily life. It is
essential that those “temporal” functions remain mediately ordered to the final
end: “in the Christian corpus the administration of the temporal things should
be undertaken, in order to bring about the realization of the purpose of the
corpus.”[43]
In other words, “in a Christian society all human actions have an essentially
religious ingredient.”[44]
What Gelasius is doing therefore, is not clarifying the relation of church and
state (as Whig Thomists suppose), but rather the relation of clerical and lay
power within the one Christian body.
In the Henotikon Zeno had implicitly
presented himself as the head of the whole Christian mundus, but Gelasius is teaching his successor that he is not
qualified for headship:
[Since] in a Christian society, of which the emperor through baptism is a member, every human action has a definite purpose and in so far has an essential religious ingredient, the emperors should submit their governmental actions to the ecclesiastical superiors.[45]
Turning to Tractate IV, Ullmann shows thatGelasius saw the purpose of the royal power in the Christian world as the
care of temporal matters, so that clerics “are not distracted by the pursuit of
these carnal matters.”[46]
Thus, Ullmann concludes,
The direction of [the] royal power by those who are, within the corporate union of Christians, qualified to do so, is as necessary as the direction of the whole body corporate. In this way this body will fulfil the purpose for which it was founded. The material or corporeal or temporal element in this body demands the guidance, that is orientation and government, by the spiritual or sacramental element of this self-same body.[47]
R.W. Dyson has shown in detail how
this Gelasian teaching on the relation of the temporal to the spiritual was
based on premises which he found in his North African tradition: in St.
Augustine’s proportioning of spiritual and carnal needs onto the offices of
bishops and Roman officials. Augustine
had not followed those principles through to their ultimate conclusions, but it
was an easy step for Gelasius to take, since it is obvious that spiritual goods
exceed bodily ones.[48]
The same point was made earlier by
Hugo Rahner:
What Augustine regarded as a lofty ideal, Gelasius made tangible: the ideal of the state as the Church’s helper, of two powers in peaceful collaboration “ruling the world”. Gelasius’ genius lay in the fact that he did not declare that the two powers deriving directly from God, Creator and Savior, should exist side by side, an impossible situation and one repugnant to God’s will, but rather that they should be hierarchically ordered, like soul and body, the spiritual superior to the material, because only in subordination is the material power’s true worth maintained.[49]
The functional division of the two
powers is not a division into separate spheres that never overlap. While
Gelasius sees the purpose of the emperor as being primarily the regulation of
temporal affairs, he is also emphatic that the emperor must use imperial force
to help the Church more directly in the preservation of the faith from charity.
In Famuli vestræ pietatis he argues
that just as Anastasius curbs popular tumults arising from secular causes, so much more should he restrain heretics,
and thereby “lead them back unto the Catholic and Apostolic communion” (§10).
He is essentially calling for the emperor to act as bracchium sæculare of the Church:
If anyone perhaps were to attempt something against public laws (perish the thought!), for no reason would you have been able to suffer it. Do you not reckon it to concern your conscience that the people subject to you should be driven back from the pure and sincere devotion of Divinity? (§10)
Far from being a Whig avant la lettre, Gelasius was in fact what we would now call an integralist.
FAMULI VESTRÆ PIETATIS
Translated by HHG et al.
Pope
Gelasius to the Emperor Anastasius.
§1 Your Piety’s servants, my sons, the
master Faustus and Irenaeus, illustrious men, and their companions who exercise
the public office of legate, when they returned to the City, said that Your
Clemency asked why I did not send my greeting to you in written form. Not, I
confess, by my design; but since those who had been dispatched a little while
ago from the regions of the East had spread [word] throughout the whole City
that they had been denied permission of seeing me by your commands, I thought
that I ought to refrain from [writing] letters, lest I be judged burdensome
rather than dutiful. You see, therefore, that it came not from my dissembling,
but rather from proper caution, lest I inflict annoyance on one minded to
reject me. But when I learned that the benevolence of Your Serenity had, as
indicated above, expected a word from my humility, then I truly recognized that
I would not unjustly be blamed if I remained silent. For, glorious son, I as a
Roman born love, honor, and accept you as the Roman Prince. And as a Christian
I desire to have knowledge according to the truth with one who has zeal for
God. And as the Vicar of the Apostolic See (of whatever quality), whenever I
see something (however little) lacking from the fullness of the Catholic Faith,
I attempt to supply it by moderate and timely suggestions. For the dispensing
of the divine word has been enjoined on me: «woe is unto me if I preach not the
gospel» (1 Cor 9:16). Because, if the vessel of election, blessed Paul the
Apostle, is afraid and cries out, how much more urgently must I fear if in my
preaching I omit anything from the ministry of preaching which has been
divinely inspired and handed down by the piety of the fathers.
§2 I pray your Piety not to judge [my]
duty toward the divine plan as arrogance. Far be it from the Roman Prince, I
beg, that he judge the truth that he senses in his heart to be an injury. For
there are two, O emperor Augustus, by which the world is principally ruled: the
sacred authority of pontiffs and the royal power. Among which how much heavier
is the burden of priests, such that they will have to render an account to the
Lord at the time of judgment even for those very kings. For you know, O most
merciful son, that although by dignity you preside over the human race,
nevertheless you devoutly bow your neck to the leaders of divine matters, and
from them you await the causes of your salvation, and you recognize that, in
partaking of the celestial sacraments, and being disposed to them (as is
appropriate), you must be submitted to the order of religion rather than rule
over it. Therefore you know that in these matters you depend on their
judgement, not willing to force them to your will. For if, inasmuch as it
pertains to the order of public discipline, even the bishops themselves obey
your laws, knowing that rule [imperium]
has been bestowed to you from on high, lest they seem in mundane things to
oppose the eminent sentence; with what passion, I ask, does it become you to
obey those, who have been assigned for the distribution of the venerable
mysteries? Just as the danger does not fall upon pontiffs lightly, to have been
silent on behalf of the cult of the Divinity, which is fitting; thus there is
no slight peril to those who (perish the thought!) when they ought to obey,
look askance. And if it is settled that the faithful submit their hearts to all
the priests in general who pass on divine things rightly, how much more must
they submit to the prelate of that See, whom the highest Divinity willed also
to be preëminent above all priests, and which the piety of the universal Church
subsequently celebrated.
§3 Clearly, wherever Your Piety turns,
no one at all has been able to raise himself to the privilege or confession of
that one, whom the voice of Christ has put over all, who has been always
confessed and venerated by the Church, and has the first devotion. Those things
which have been constituted by divine judgement can be attacked by human
presumption, but they cannot be conquered by any power. And if only boldness would
not be so pernicious against those struggling, as those things which have been
fixed by the very founder of sacred religion cannot be dislodged by any force:
the foundation of God stands firm (2 Tim 2:19). For is religion, when it is
infested by some [persons], able to be overcome by novelties? Does it not
rather remain unconquered by the thing supposed to be able to defeat it? And I
ask you therefore, may they desist, who under your aegis run about headlong
seeking the disruption of the church, which is not permitted: or at least that
these should in no way achieve those things which they wickedly desire, and not
keep their measure before God and men.
§4 For this reason, before God, I beg,
adjure, and exhort your piety purely and earnestly that you not receive my
request disdainfully: I say again: I ask that you hear me beseeching you now in
this life rather than (later) accusing you—perish the thought!—before the
divine tribunal. Nor is it hidden from me, O Emperor Augustus, what the
devotion of Your Piety has been in private life. You always chose to be a
participator of the eternal promise. Wherefore, I pray you, be not angry with
me, if I love you so much that I want you to have that reign, which you have
temporarily, forever, and that you who rule the age, might be able to rule with
Christ. Certainly, by your laws, Emperor, you do not allow anything to perish,
nor do you allow any damage to be done to the Roman name. Surely then it is not
true, Excellent Prince, who desires not only the present benefits of Christ but
also the future ones, that you would suffer anyone under your aegis to bring
loss to religion, to truth, to the sincerity of the Catholic Communion, and to
the Faith? By what faith (I ask you) will you ask reward of him there, whose
loss you do not prohibit here?
§5 Be they not heavy, I pray thee,
those things that are said for your eternal salvation. You have read it
written: «the wounds of a friend are better than the kisses of an enemy» (Prov.
27:8). I ask your piety to receive what I say into your mind in the same
sentiment in which I say it. No one should deceive Your Piety. What the
Scriptures witness figuratively through the prophet is true: «One is my dove,
one is my perfect one» (Cant. 6:8), one is the Christian faith, which is Catholic.
But that faith is truly Catholic, which is divided by a sincere, pure, and
unspotted communion from all the perfidious and their successors and
associates. Otherwise there would not be the divinely commanded distinction,
but a deplorable muddle. Nor would there be any reason left, if we allow this
contagion in anyone, not to open wide the gate to all the heresies. For who in
one thing offends, is guilty of all (James 2:10); and: who despises little
things shall little by little fall (Sirach 19:1)
§6 This is what the Apostolic See
vigorously guards against, that since the pure root is the glorious confession
of the Apostle, it might not be soiled by any fissure of perversity, nor by any
direct contagion. For if something like that were to happen (which God forbid,
and which we trust is impossible), how could we dare to resist any error, or
from whence could we request the correction to those in error? Moreover, if
Your Piety denies that the people of a single city can be brought together in
peace, what would we do with the whole world, if (God forbid) it were to be
deceived by our prevarication? If the whole world has been set right, despising
the profane traditions of its fathers, how could the people of a single city
not be converted if the preaching of the faith persevere. Therefore, glorious
Emperor, do I not will the peace, I who would embrace it even if it came at the
price of my blood? But, I prithee, let us hold in our mind of what sort the
peace ought to be; not any kind, but a truly Christian peace. For how can there
be a true peace where chaste charity is lacking? But how charity ought to be,
the Apostle evidently preaches for us, who says, Charity is from a pure heart,
and a good conscience, and an unfeigned faith (1 Tim. 1:5). How, I pray thee,
shall it be from a pure heart, if it is poisoned by an external contagion? How
shall it be from a good conscience, if it is commingled with depraved and evil
things? How shall it be from an unfeigned faith if it remains united with the
perfidious? While these things have often been said by us, it is nevertheless
necessary to repeat them incessantly, and not to be silent as long as the name
of “peace” continues to be put forward as an excuse; it is not for us (as the
is enviously asserted) to make “peace”, but we nevertheless teach that we want
that true peace, which is the only peace, apart from which none other can be
shown.
§7 Certainly if the dogma of Eutyches,
against which the caution of the Apostolic See vigilantly watches, is believed
to be consistent with the saving Catholic faith, then it ought to be brought
forward plainly and asserted and supported with as much force as possible, for
then it will be possible to show not only how inimical it is to the Christian
faith itself, but also how many and how deadly are the heresies it contains in
its dregs. But if rather (as we are confident you will) you judge that this
dogma should be excluded from Catholic minds, I ask you why you do not also
suppress the contagion of those who have been shown to be contaminated by it?
As the Apostle says: Are only those who do things that ought not to be done
guilty, and not also they that consent to them that do them? (cf. Rom 1:32).
Accordingly, just as one cannot accept a participant in perversity without
equally approving of the perversity, so too, one cannot refute perversity while
admitting an accomplice and partisan of perversity.
§8 Certainly, by your laws,
accomplices of crimes and harbourers of thieves are judged to be bound equally
by the same punishment; nor is he considered to have no part in a crime, who,
though he did not do it himself, nevertheless accepts the familiarity and the
alliance of the doer. Accordingly, when the Council of Chalcedon, celebrated
for the Catholic and Apostolic faith and the true communion, condemned
Eutyches, the progenitor of those detestable ravings, it did not leave it at
that, but likewise also struck down his consort Dioscorus and the rest. In this
way, therefore, just as in the case of every heresy there is no ambiguity about
what has always been done or what is being done: their successors Timothy [the
Cat], Peter [the Hoarse], and the other Peter, the Antiochian, have been cut
out— not individually by councils called again to deal with them singly, but
once and for all as a consequence of the regular acts of the synod. Therefore,
as it has not been clear that even those who were their correspondents and
accomplices are all bound with a similar strictness, and are by right wholly
separated from the Catholic and Apostolic communion, We hereby declare that
Acacius, too, is to be removed from communion with Us, since he preferred to
cast in his lot with perfidy rather than to remain in the authentic Catholic
and Apostolic communion (though for almost three years he has been authoritatively
advised by letters of the Apostolic See, lest it should come to this). But
after he went over to another communion, nothing was possible except that he
should be at once cut off from association with the Apostolic See, lest on his
account, if We delayed even a little, We also should seem to have come into
contact with the perfidious. But when he was struck with such a blow, did he
come to his senses, did he promise correction, did he emend his error? Would he
have been coerced by more lenient treatment, when even harsh blows left no
impression? While he tarries in his perfidy and damnation, it is both
impossible to use his name in the liturgy of the church, and unnecessary to
tolerate any external contact with him. Wherefore he will be led in good faith
away from the heretical communion into which he has mixed himself, or there
will be no choice but to drive him away with them.
§9 But if the bishops of the East
murmur, that the Apostolic See did not apply such judgments to them, as if they
had either convinced the Apostolic See that Peter [the Hoarse] was to be
accepted as legitimate, or had not yet been fully complicit in this unheard-of
acceptation: just as they cannot demonstrate that he was free of heretical
depravity, neither can they in anyway excuse themselves, being in communion
with heretics. If perhaps they should add that they all with one voice reported
the reception of Peter [the Hoarse] by Acacius to the Apostolic See, then by
the same token they know how he responded to them. But the authority of the
Apostolic See— that in all Christian ages it has been set over the universal
Church— is confirmed both by a series of canons of the Fathers, and by manifold
tradition. But even hence, whether anyone should prevail to usurp anything for
himself against the ordinances of the Synod of Nicaea, this can be shown to the
college of the one communion, not to the opinion of external society. If anyone
has confidence amongst them, let him go out into the midst, and disprove and
instruct the Apostolic See concerning each part. Therefore let his name
[Acacius] be removed from our midst, which works the separation of churches far
from Catholic communion, in order that sincere peace of faith and of communion
should be repaired, and unity: and then let it competently and legitimately be
investigated which of us either has risen up or struggles to rise up against
venerable antiquity. And then shall appear who by modest intention guards the
form and tradition of the elders, and who irreverently leaping beyond these,
reckons himself able to become equal by robbery.
§10 But if it is proposed to me that
the character [persona] of the
Constantinopolitan people makes it impossible (it is said) that the name of
scandal, that is Acacius, be removed; I am silent, because with both the
heretic Macedonius formerly having been driven out, and Nestorius recently
having been thrown out, the Constantinopolitan people have elected to remain
Catholic rather than be retained by affection for their condemned greater
prelates. I am silent, because those who had been baptized by these very same
condemned prelates, remaining in the Catholic faith, are disturbed by no
agitation. I am silent, because for ludicrous things the authority of Your
Piety now restrains popular tumults; and thus much more for the necessary
salvation of their souls the multitude of the Constantinopolitan city obeys
you, if you princes should lead them back unto the Catholic and Apostolic
communion. For, Emperor Augustus, if anyone perhaps were to attempt something
against public laws (perish the thought!), for no reason would you have been
able to suffer it. Do you not reckon it to concern your conscience that the
people subject to you should be driven back from the pure and sincere devotion
of Divinity? Finally, if the mind of the people of one city is not reckoned to
be offended if divine things (as the matter demands) are corrected— how much
more does it hold that, lest divine things should be offended, we ought not
(nor can we) strike the pious faith of all those of the Catholic name?
§11 And nevertheless these same ones
demand that they should be healed by our will. Therefore they allow that they
can be cured by competent remedies: otherwise (Heaven forfend!) by crossing
over into their ruin, we can perish with them, whereas we cannot save them. Now
here I leave to your conscience under divine judgement what must rather be
done: whether, as We desire, we should return all at once unto certain life;
or, as those demand, we should tend unto manifest death.
§12 But still
they strain to call the Apostolic See proud and arrogant for furnishing them
with medicines. The quality of the languishing often has this: that they should
accuse rather the medics calling them back to healthful things by fitting
observations, than that they themselves should consent to depose or reprove
their noxious appetites. If we are proud, because we minister fitting remedies
of souls, what are those to be called who resist? If we are proud who say that
obedience must be given to paternal decrees, by what name should those be
called who oppose them? If we are puffed up, who desire that the divine cult
should be served with pure and unblemished tenor; let them say how those who
think even against divinity should be named. Thus also do the rest, who are in
error, reckon us, because we do not consent to their insanity. Nevertheless,
truth herself indicates where the spirit of pride really stands and fights.
[1] Sometimes also as Ad Anastasium, Epistle XII (Thiel), or Epistle VIII (Migne).
[2] Matthew Briel, trans. in:
George E. Demacopoulos, The Invention of
Peter: Apostolic Discourse and Papal Authority in Late Antiquity (Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 2013), pp. 173-180; Bronwen Neil and Pauline
Allen, trans., The Letters of Gelasius I
(492-496) (Turnhout: Brepols, 2014), pp. 73-80.
[3] The translation was made by
numerous online friends of The Josias in
a shared google spreadsheet. The style is therefore uneven. For technical
reasons we used Migne’s edition in PL
59, col. 41-47, but we have corrected it in some places with reference to
Thiel’s critical edition: Andreas Thiel, ed., Epistolae Romanorum pontificum genuinae et quae ad eos scriptae sunt: a
S. Hilaro usque ad Pelagium II., vol. 1 (Braunsberg: E. Peter, 1867), pp.
349-358. For the paragraph numbering we have followed Thiel.
[4] For an account of the period,
see: Guy Halsall, Barbarian Migrations
and the Roman West, 376–568 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007),
chs. 9-10.
[5] Neil and Allen, trans., The Letters of Gelasius I, Introduction.
[6] Neil and Allen, trans., The Letters of Gelasius I, p. 71.
[7] Hugo Rahner, S.J., Church and State in Early Christianity, trans.
Leo Donald Davis, S.J. (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1961), p. 151. As Rahner
notes, his book was originally written at a time “when the struggle between
Church and state in Nazi Germany was at its height” (p. xi), which goes someway
in explaining
its tone.
[8] Bronwen
Neil and Pauline Allen call it “sententious and pompous” and complain that it
is repetitive and overburdens subordinate clauses: The Letters of Gelasius I, p. 67.
[9] George Demacopoulos portrays
him as an ineffectual blusterer The
Invention of Peter, ch. 3.
[10] See: Aloysius K. Ziegler,
“Pope Gelasius I and His Teaching on the Relation of Church and State,” in: The Catholic Historical Review 27.4
(1942), pp. 412-437, at pp. 416-417.
[11] Thiel’s edition contains 43
letters, 49 fragments, and six tractates, filling over 300 pages: Thiel, Epistolae, vol. 1, pp. 285-618.
[12] See: Mario
Spinelli, s.v. “Gelasius I,” in: Lexikon
für Theologie und Kirche, 3rd ed., vol. IV, eds. Walter Kasper, et al. (Freiburg:
Herder, 1995), col. 401-402.
[13] Dioscurus had (verbally)
agreed with Eutyches that there was only one nature in Christ. In Alexandria
this was held to be the orthodox position, since St. Cyril of Alexandria had
used the formula μία φύσις τοῦ θεοῦ λόγου σεσαρκωμένη (“one incarnate nature of God
the Logos”). Chalcedon, however, defined that Christ was in two natures (ἐν δύο φύσεσιν). It is now generally held
that the disagreement is based on an equivocal use of the word φύσις (nature). See: Theresia
Hainthaler, s.v. “Monophysitismus,” in: Lexikon
für Theologie und Kirche, vol. VII, (1998), col. 418-421; W. H. C. Frend, The Rise of the Monophysite Movement:
Chapters in the History of the Church in the Fifth and Sixth Centuries
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972).
[14] Frend, The Rise of the Monophysite Movement, p. 155.
[15] Frend, The Rise of the Monophysite Movement,, p. 174.
[16] For the story of the Henotikon
see: Ibid., pp. 174-183.
[17] Zeno, Henotikon, in: The
Ecclesiastical History of Evagrius Scholasticus, trans. Michael Whitby
(Liverpool: Liverpool University Press, 2000), III,14; pp. 147-149, at p. 147.
[18] Zeno, Henotikon, p. 149.
[19] One of the orthodox “Sleepless
Monks” was able to pin the pope’s excommunication to Acacius’s vestments during
the celebration of the Divine Liturgy: Frend, The Rise of the Monophysite Movement, pp. 182-183.
[20] Frend, The Rise of the Monophysite Movement,, p. 190.
[21] Neil and Allen, trans., The Letters of Gelasius I, pp. 37-38.
[22] Rahner, Church and State, pp. 154-155.
[23] See: Brian Tierney, The Crisis of Church and State (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 1988), p. 10; Robert Louis Benson, “The Gelasian
Doctrine: Uses And Transformations,” in: George Makdisi, et al., eds., La notion d’autorité au Moyen Age: Islam,
Byzance, Occident: Colloques internationaux de La Napoule, session des 23-26
octobre 1978 (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1982), pp. 13-44.
[24] See: John Courtney Murray,
S.J., We Hold These Truths: Catholic
Reflections on the American Proposition (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1960),
especially pp. 202-203; George Weigel, “Catholicism and Democracy: Parsing the
Other Twentieth-Century Revolution,” in: Michael Novak, William Brailsford, and
Cornelis Heesters, eds. A Free Society
Reader: Principles for the New Millennium (Lanham: Lexington Books, 2000),
pp. 141-165, at pp. 150-151. Cf. my critique of the Whig Thomists: “Integralism
and Gelasian Dyarchy,” in: The Josias,
March 3, 2016: https://thejosias.com/2016/03/03/integralism-and-gelasian-dyarchy
(accessed March 28, 2020), part 4.
[25] Erich
Caspar, Geschichte des Papsttums von den
Anfängen bis zur Höhe der Weltherrschaft, vol. 2 (Tübingen: Mohr-Siebeck,
1933), p. 67 (translation my own).
[26] Alan Cottrell, “Auctoritas and Potestas: A Reevaluation of the Correspondence of Gelasius I on
Papal-Imperial Relations,” in: Medieval
Studies 55 (1993), pp. 95-109, at p. 96. (This is not Cottrell’s own view).
[27] Michael Hanby, “For and
Against Integralism,” in: First Things 301.4
(2020), pp. 43-50. Hanby does not explicitly mention Gelasius, but it is clear
that the Gelasian teaching is in the background of his discussion of auctoritas and potestas, especially since he quotes Walter Ullmann’s
interpretation of Gelasius (p. 45).
[28] Hanby, “For and Against
Integralism,” p. 45.
[29] Hanby, “For and Against
Integralism,” p. 45.
[30] Walter Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government in the Middle
Ages: A Study in the Ideological Relation of Clerical to Lay Power, 2nd ed.
(London: Methuen, 1962), pp. 12-13, note 5.
[31] Caspar, Geschichte des Papsttums, p. 66.
[32] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 21.
[33] Ernst Stein, “La Période
Byzantine de la Papauté,” in: The Catholic
Historical Review 21.2 (1935), pp. 129-163, at p. 135. Hanby complains
about me: “Waldstein does not think philosophically about the distinction
between auctoritas and potestas, which he treats more or less
synonymously” (Hanby, “For and Against Integralism,” p. 47). I wonder if he
would make the same complaint about St. Gelasius in Tractate IV.
[34] Ziegler, “Pope Gelasius I and
His Teaching,” p. 432, note 66; the quotation from Felix can be found in:
Thiel, Epistolae, vol. 1, p. 272;
translation in: Jeffrey Richards, The
Popes and the Papacy in the Early Middle Ages, 476-752 (London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1979), p. 62.
[35] In the light of the subsequent development
of Church teaching one could save something like Erich Caspar’s interpretation
as follows: The relationship between the spiritual and temporal powers in temporal matters would be modeled on
the relationship between the senate and the magistrates in the Republic. Auctoritas would mean moral authority. Potestas would be coercive force, prescinding from whether it is united to
moral authority or not. So it would be wrong to see potestas as mere violence but violence would be included as well as
rightly ordered force. The pope would have both auctoritas and potestas
in the spiritual order. In the temporal order he would exercise auctorias, and his auctoritas would guarantee the right order of the potestas of temporal rulers. See: Thomas
Crean and Alan Fimister, Integralism: A
Manual of Political Philosophy (Neunkirchen-Seelscheid: Editiones
Scholasticae, 2020), p. 72.
[36] Demacopoulos, The Invention of Peter, p. 90.
[37] Demacopoulos, The Invention of Peter, pp. 8-9.
[38] John Henry Newman, An Essay on the Development of Christian Doctrine, 8th ed. (London:
Longmans, Green, and co., 1891), p. 40.
[39] Demacopoulos, The Invention of Peter, pp. 90-91; cf.
Ullmann’s similar argument in The Growth
of Papal Government, pp. 23-26.
[40] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 28.
[41] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 11.
[42] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 3.
[43] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 12.
[44] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 20.
[45] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 22.
[46] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 24.
[47] Ullmann, The Growth of Papal Government, p. 28.
[48] Robert W. Dyson, St. Augustine of Hippo: The Christian
Transformation of Political Philosophy (London: Continuum, 2005), ch. 5.
[49] Rahner, Church and State, p. 157.